组合数学 (Fall 2011)/Extremal set theory II and 组合数学 (Fall 2011)/Problem set 3: Difference between pages

From TCS Wiki
(Difference between pages)
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>WikiSysop
(Created page with '== Sauer's lemma and VC-dimension == === Shattering and the VC-dimension === {{Theorem|Definition (shatter)| :Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math> be set family and let <ma…')
 
imported>Etone
 
Line 1: Line 1:
== Sauer's lemma and VC-dimension ==
== Problem 1==


=== Shattering and the VC-dimension ===
==Problem 2==
{{Theorem|Definition (shatter)|
一个图 <math>G(V,E)</math> 的切 (cut) 是一个边集 <math>C\subseteq E</math>,使得去掉这些边之后 <math>G</math> 不再连通。
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math> be set family and let <math>R\subseteq X</math> be a subset. The '''trace''' of <math>\mathcal{F}</math> on <math>R</math>, denoted <math>\mathcal{F}|_R</math> is defined as
::<math>\mathcal{F}|_R=\{S\cap R\mid S\in\mathcal{F}\}</math>.
:We say that <math>\mathcal{F}</math> '''shatters''' <math>R</math> if <math>\mathcal{F}|_R=2^R</math>, i.e. for all <math>T\subseteq R</math>, there exists an <math>S\in\mathcal{F}</math> such that <math>T=S\cap R</math>.
}}


The [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/VC_dimension '''VC dimension'''] is defined by the power of a family to shatter a set.
证明:任意一个有 <math>m</math> 条边的无向图都存在一个大小为 <math>\frac{m}{2}</math> 的切。


{{Theorem|Definition (VC-dimension)|
==Problem 3 ==
:The '''Vapnik–Chervonenkis dimension''' ('''VC-dimension''') of a set family <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math>, denoted <math>\text{VC-dim}(\mathcal{F})</math>, is the size of the largest <math>R\subseteq X</math> shattered by <math>\mathcal{F}</math>.
<math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq{[n]\choose k}</math> 为一个 <math>k</math>-regular family,即 <math>\forall i\in[n]</math>,刚好有 <math>k</math> 个不同的 <math>S\in\mathcal{F}</math> 满足 <math>i\in S</math>。
}}


It is a core concept in [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Computational_learning_theory computational learning theory].
假设 <math>k\ge 10</math>。证明:存在一个对 <math>[n]</math> 的 2着色 <math>f:[n]\rightarrow\{0,1\}</math> 使得 <math>\mathcal{F}</math> 中不存在单色的集合 <math>S\in\mathcal{F}</math>
 
Each subset <math>S\subseteq X</math> can be equivalently represented by its characteristic function <math>f_S:X\rightarrow\{0,1\}</math>, such that for each <math>x\in X</math>,
:<math>f_S(x)=\begin{cases}
1 & x\in S\\
0 & x\not\in S.
\end{cases}</math>
 
Then a set family <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq2^X</math> corresponds to a collection of boolean functions <math>\{f_S\mid S\in\mathcal{F}\}</math>, which is a subset of all Boolean functions in the form <math>f:X\rightarrow\{0,1\}</math>. We wonder on how large a subdomain <math>Y\subseteq X</math>, <math>\mathcal{F}</math> includes all the <math>2^{|Y|}</math> mappings <math>Y\rightarrow\{0,1\}</math>. The largest size of such subdomain is the VC-dimension. It measures how complicated a collection of boolean functions (or equivalently a set family) is.
 
=== Sauer's Lemma ===
The definition of the VC-dimension involves enumerating all subsets, thus is difficult to analyze in general. The following famous result state a very simple sufficient condition to lower bound the VC-dimension, regarding only the size of the family. The lemma is due to Sauer, and independently due to Shelah and Perles. A slightly weaker version is found by Vapnik and Chervonenkis, who use the framework to develop a theory of classifications.
 
{{Theorem|Sauer's Lemma (Sauer; Shelah-Perles; Vapnik-Chervonenkis)|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math> where <math>|X|=n</math>. If <math>|\mathcal{F}|>\sum_{1\le i<k}{n\choose i}</math>, then there exists an <math>R\in{X\choose k}</math> such that <math>\mathcal{F}</math> shatters <math>R</math>.
}}
In other words, for any set family <math>\mathcal{F}</math> with <math>|\mathcal{F}|>\sum_{1\le i<k}{n\choose i}</math>, its VC-dimension <math>\text{VC-dim}(\mathcal{F})\ge k</math>.
 
=== Hereditary family ===
We note the Sauer's lemma is especially easy to prove for a special type of set families, called the '''hereditary''' families.
{{Theorem|Definition (hereditary family)|
:A set system <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math> is said to be '''hereditary''' (also called an '''ideal''' or an '''abstract simplicial complex'''), if
::<math>S\subseteq T\in\mathcal{F}</math> implies <math>S\in\mathcal{F}</math>.
}}
In other words, for a hereditary family <math>\mathcal{F}</math>, if <math>R\in\mathcal{F}</math>, then all subsets of <math>R</math> are also in <math>\mathcal{F}</math>. An immediate consequence is the following proposition.
{{Theorem|Proposition|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}</math> be a hereditary family. If <math>R\in\mathcal{F}</math> then <math>\mathcal{F}</math> shatters <math>R</math>.
}}
 
Therefore, it is very easy to prove the Sauer's lemma for hereditary families:
{{Theorem|Lemma|
:For <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math>, <math>|X|=n</math>, if <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is hereditary and <math>|\mathcal{F}|>\sum_{1\le i<k}{n\choose i}</math> then there exists an <math>R\in{X\choose k}</math> such that <math>\mathcal{F}</math> shatters <math>R</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
Since <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is hereditary, we only need to show that there exists an <math>R\in\mathcal{F}</math> of size <math>|R|\ge k</math>, which must be true, because if all members of <math>\mathcal{F}</math> are of sizes <math><k</math>, then <math>|\mathcal{F}|\le\left|\bigcup_{1\le i<k}{X\choose k}\right|=\sum_{1\le i<k}{n\choose i}</math>, a contradiction.
}}
 
To prove the Sauer's lemma for general non-hereditary families, we can use some way to reduce arbitrary families to hereditary families. Here we apply the shifting technique to achieve this.
 
=== Down-shifts ===
Note that we work on <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq2^X</math>, instead of <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq{X\choose k}</math> like in the Erdős–Ko–Rado theorem, so we do not need to preserve the size of member sets. Instead, we need to reduce an arbitrary family to a hereditary one, thus we use a shift operator which replaces a member set by a subset of it.
{{Theorem|Definition (down-shifts)|
: Assume <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^{[n]}</math>, and <math>i\in[n]</math>. Define the '''down-shift''' operator <math>S_{i}</math> as follows:
:* for each <math>T\in\mathcal{F}</math>, let
::<math>S_{i}(T)=
\begin{cases}
T\setminus\{i\} & \mbox{if }i\in T \mbox{ and }T\setminus\{i\} \not\in\mathcal{F},\\
T & \mbox{otherwise;}
\end{cases}</math>
:* let <math>S_{i}(\mathcal{F})=\{S_{i}(T)\mid T\in \mathcal{F}\}</math>.
}}
 
Repeatedly applying <math>S_i</math> to <math>\mathcal{F}</math> for all <math>i\in[n]</math>, due to the finiteness, eventually <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is not changed by any <math>S_i</math>. We call such a family '''down-shifted'''. A family <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is down-shifted if and only if <math>S_i(\mathcal{F})=\mathcal{F}</math> for all <math>i\in[n]</math>. It is then easy to see that a down-shifted <math>\mathcal{F}</math> must be hereditary.
 
{{Theorem|Theorem|
:If <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq2^X</math> is down-shifted, then <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is hereditary.
}}
 
In order to use down-shift to prove the Sauer's lemma, we need to make sure that down-shift does not decrease <math>|\mathcal{F}|</math> and does not increase the VC-dimension <math>\text{VC-dim}(\mathcal{F})</math>.
 
{{Theorem|Proposition|
# <math>|S_{i}(\mathcal{F})|=\mathcal{F}</math>;
# <math>|S_i(\mathcal{F})|_R|\le |\mathcal{F}|_R|</math>, thus if <math>S_{i}(\mathcal{F})</math> shatters an <math>R</math>, so does <math>\mathcal{F}</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
(1) is immediate. To prove (2), it is sufficient to prove that <math>S_i(\mathcal{F})|_R\subseteq S_i(\mathcal{F}|_R)</math> and then apply (1).
 
[[file:Down-shift-property.png|600px]]
}}
 
;Proof of Sauer's lemma
Now we can prove the Sauer's lemma for arbitrary <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^{[n]}</math>.
 
For any <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^{[n]}</math>, repeatedly apply <math>S_i</math> for all <math>i\in</math> till the family is down-shifted, which is denoted by <math>\mathcal{F}'</math>. We have proved that <math>|\mathcal{F}'|=|\mathcal{F}|>\sum_{1\le i<k}{n\choose i}</math> and <math>\mathcal{F}'</math> is hereditary, thus as argued before, here exists an <math>R</math> of size <math>k</math> shattered by <math>\mathcal{F}'</math>. By the above proposition, <math>|\mathcal{F}'|_R|\le |\mathcal{F}|_R|</math>, thus <math>\mathcal{F}</math> also shatters <math>R</math>. The lemma is proved.
 
<math>\square</math>
 
== The Kruskal–Katona Theorem ==
The '''shadow''' of a set system <math>\mathcal{F}</math>, denoted <math>\Delta\mathcal{F}</math>, consists of all sets  which can be obtained by removing an element from a set in <math>\mathcal{F}</math>.
 
{{Theorem|Definition|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq {X\choose k}</math>. The '''shadow''' of <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is defined to be
::<math>\Delta\mathcal{F}=\left\{T\in {X\choose k-1}\,\,\bigg|\,\, \exists S\in\mathcal{F}\mbox{ such that } T\subset S\right\}</math>.
}}
 
The shadow contains rich information about the set system. An extremal question is: for a system of fixed number of <math>k</math>-sets, how small can its shadow be? The Kruskal–Katona theorem gives an answer to this question.
 
To state the result of the Kruskal–Katona theorem, we need to introduce the concepts of the <math>k</math>-cascade representation of numbers and the colex order of sets.
 
=== <math>k</math>-cascade representation of a number ===
{{Theorem|Theorem|
:Given positive integers <math>m</math> and <math>k</math>, there exists a unique representation of <math>m</math> in the form
::<math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}=\sum_{\ell=t}^k{m_\ell\choose \ell}</math>,
:where <math>m_k>m_{k-1}>\cdots>m_t\ge t\ge 1</math>.
:This representation of <math>m</math> is called a '''<math>k</math>-cascade''' (or a '''<math>k</math>-binomial''') representation of <math>m</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
In fact, the <math>k</math>-cascade representation <math>(m_k,m_{k-1},\ldots,m_t)</math> of an <math>m</math> can be found by the following simple greedy algorithm:
<math>\ell=k;</math>
while (<math>m>0</math>) do
    let <math>m_\ell</math> be the largest integer for which <math>{m_\ell\choose \ell}\le m;</math>
    <math>m=m-m_\ell;</math>
    <math>\ell=\ell-1;</math>
end
 
We then show that the above algorithm constructs a sequence <math>(m_k,m_{k-1},\ldots,m_t)</math> with <math>m_k>m_{k-1}>\cdots>m_t\ge t\ge 1</math>.
 
Suppose the current <math>\ell</math> and the current <math>m</math>. To see that <math>m_{\ell-1}< m_\ell</math>, we suppose otherwise <math>m_{\ell-1}\ge m_\ell</math>. Then
:<math>m\ge {m_\ell\choose \ell}+{m_{\ell-1}\choose \ell-1}\ge{m_\ell\choose \ell}+{m_{\ell}\choose \ell-1}={1+m_{\ell}\choose \ell}</math>
contradicting the maximality of <math>m_\ell</math>. Therefore, <math>m_\ell>m_{\ell-1}</math>.
 
The algorithm continues reducing <math>m</math> to smaller nonnegative values, and eventually reaches a stage where the choice of <math>m_t</math> for some <math>t\ge 2</math> where <math>{m_t\choose t}</math> equals the current <math>m</math>; or gets right down to choosing <math>m_1</math> as the integer such that <math>m_1={m_1\choose 1}</math> equals the current <math>m</math>.
 
Therefore,  <math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}</math> and <math>m_k>m_{k-1}>\cdots>m_t\ge t\ge 1</math>.
 
The uniqueness of the <math>k</math>-cascade representation follows by the induction on <math>k</math>.
 
When <math>k=1</math>, <math>m</math> has a unique <math>k</math>-cascade representation <math>m={m\choose 1}</math>.
 
For general <math>k>1</math>, suppose that every nonnegative integer <math>m</math> has a unique <math>(k-1)</math>-cascade representation.
 
Suppose then that <math>m</math> has two <math>k</math>-cascade representations:
:<math>m={a_k\choose k}+{a_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{a_t\choose t}={b_k\choose k}+{b_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{b_r\choose r}</math>.
We then show that it must hold that <math>a_k=b_k</math>.
If <math>a_k\neq b_k</math>, WLOG, suppose that <math>a_k<b_k</math>. We obtain
:<math>
\begin{align}
m&
={a_k\choose k}+{a_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{a_t\choose t}\\
&\le {a_k\choose k}+{a_{k}-1\choose k-1}+\cdots+{a_k-(k-t)\choose t}+\cdots+{a_k-k+1\choose 1}\\
&={a_k+1\choose k}-1,
\end{align}</math>
where the last equation is got by repeatedly applying the identity
:<math>{n\choose k}+{n\choose k-1}={n+1\choose k}</math>.
We then obtain
:<math>m<{a_k+1\choose k}\le{b_k\choose k}\le m</math>,
which is a contradiction. Therefore, <math>a_k=b_k</math>, and by the induction hypothesis, the remaining value <math>m-a_k=m-b_k</math> has a unique <math>(k-1)</math>-cascade representation, so <math>a_i=b_i</math> for all <math>i</math>.
}}
 
=== Co-lexicographic order of subsets ===
The co-lexicographic order of sets plays a particularly important role in the investigation of the size of the shadow of a system of <math>k</math>-sets.
{{Theorem|Definition|
: The '''co-lexicographic (colex) order''' (also called the '''reverse lexicographic order''') of sets is defined as follows: for any <math>A,B\subseteq [n]</math>, <math>A\neq B</math>,
::<math>A<B</math> if <math>\max A\setminus B < \max B\setminus A</math>.
}}
 
We can sort sets in colex order by first writing each set as a tuple, whose elements are in decreasing order, and then sorting the tuples in the lexicographic order of tuples.
 
For example, <math>{[5]\choose 3}</math> in colex order is
{3,2,1}
{4,2,1}
{4,3,1}
{4,3,2}
{5,2,1}
{5,3,1}
{5,3,2}
{5,4,1}
{5,4,2}
{5,4,3}
 
We find that the first <math>{n\choose 3}</math> sets in this order for <math>n=3,4,5</math>, form precisely <math>{[n]\choose 3}</math>. And if we write the colex order of <math>{[6]\choose 3}</math>, the above colex order of <math>{[5]\choose 3}</math> appears as a prefix of that order. Elaborating on this, we have:
{{Theorem|Proposition|
:Let <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> be the first <math>m</math> sets in the colex order of <math>{\mathbb{N}\choose k}</math>. Then
::<math>\mathcal{R}\left({n\choose k},k\right)={[n]\choose k}</math>,
:that is, the first <math>{n\choose k}</math> sets in the colex order of all <math>k</math>-sets of natural numbers is precisely <math>{[n]\choose k}</math>.
}}
 
This proposition says that the sets in <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> is highly overlapped, which suggests that <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> may have small shadow. The size of the shadow of <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> is closely related to the <math>k</math>-cascade representation of <math>m</math>.
 
{{Theorem|Theorem|
:Suppose the <math>k</math>-cascade representation of <math>m</math> is
::<math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}</math>.
:Then
::<math>|\Delta\mathcal{R}(m,k)|={m_k\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t-1}</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
Given <math>m</math> and its <math>k</math>-cascade representation <math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}</math>, the <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> is constructed as:
* all sets in <math>{[m_k]\choose k}</math>;
* all sets in <math>{[m_{k-1}]\choose k-1}</math>, unioned with <math>\{1+m_k\}\,</math>;
::<math>\vdots</math>
* all sets in <math>{[m_{t}]\choose t}</math>, unioned with <math>\{1+m_k,1+m_{k-1},\ldots,1+m_{t+1}\}</math>.
The shadow <math>\Delta\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math> is the collection of all <math>(k-1)</math>-sets contained by the above sets, which are
* all sets in <math>{[m_k]\choose k-1}</math>;
* all sets in <math>{[m_{k-1}]\choose k-2}</math>, unioned with <math>\{1+m_k\}\,</math>;
::<math>\vdots</math>
* all sets in <math>{[m_{t}]\choose t-1}</math>, unioned with <math>\{1+m_k,1+m_{k-1},\ldots,1+m_{t+1}\}</math>.
Thus,
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{R}(m,k)|={m_k\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t-1}</math>.
}}
 
=== The Kruskal–Katona theorem ===
The Kruskal–Katona theorem states that among all systems of <math>m</math> <math>k</math>-sets, <math>\mathcal{R}(m,k)</math>, i.e., the first <math>m</math> <math>k</math>-sets in the colex order, has the smallest shadow.
 
The theorem is proved independently by Joseph Kruskal in 1963 and G.O.H. Katona in 1966, and is a fundamental result in finite set theory and combinatorial topology.
{{Theorem|Theorem (Kruskal 1963, Katona 1966)|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq {X\choose k}</math> with <math>|\mathcal{F}|=m</math>, and suppose that
::<math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}</math>
:where <math>m_k>m_{k-1}>\cdots>m_t\ge t\ge 1</math>. Then
::<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}|\ge {m_k\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t-1}</math>.
}}
 
The <math>f</math>-vector of a set system <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^X</math> is a vector <math>(|\mathcal{F}_0|,|\mathcal{F}_1|,\ldots,|\mathcal{F}_n|)</math> where
:<math>\mathcal{F}_k=\{S\mid S\in\mathcal{F}, |S|=k\}</math>,
i.e., the <math>f</math>-vector gives the number of member sets of each size.
 
In a hereditary family (also called an [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Abstract_simplicial_complex abstract simplicial complex]), <math>\mathcal{F}_k</math> is formed by the shadow of <math>\mathcal{F}_{k+1}</math> as well as some additional <math>k</math>-sets introduced in this level. The Kruskal-Katona theorem gives a lower bound on <math>|\mathcal{F}_i|</math>, given the <math>|\mathcal{F}_{i-1}|</math>.
 
The original proof of the theorem is rather complicated. In the following years, several different proofs were discovered. Here we present a proof dueto Frankl by the shifting technique.
 
;Frankl's shifting proof of Kruskal-Katonal theorem (Frankl 1984)
 
We take the classic <math>(i,j)</math>-shift operator <math>S_{ij}</math> defined in the original proof of the Erdős-Ko-Rado theorem.
{{Theorem|Definition (<math>(i,j)</math>-shift)|
: Assume <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq 2^{[n]}</math>, and <math>0\le i<j\le n-1</math>. Define the '''<math>(i,j)</math>-shift''' <math>S_{ij}</math> as an operator on <math>\mathcal{F}</math> as follows:
:*for each <math>T\in\mathcal{F}</math>, write <math>T_{ij}=(T\setminus\{j\})\cup\{i\} </math>, and let
::<math>S_{ij}(T)=
\begin{cases}
T_{ij} & \mbox{if }j\in T, i\not\in T, \mbox{ and }T_{ij} \not\in\mathcal{F},\\
T & \mbox{otherwise;}
\end{cases}</math>
:* let <math>S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})=\{S_{ij}(T)\mid T\in \mathcal{F}\}</math>.
}}
 
It is immediate that shifting does not change the size of the set or the size of the system, i.e., <math>|S_{ij}(T)|=|T|\,</math> and  <math>|S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})|=\mathcal{F}</math>. And due to the finiteness, repeatedly applying <math>(i,j)</math>-shifts for any <math>1\le i<j\le n</math>, eventually <math>\mathcal{F}</math> does not changing any more. We called such an <math>\mathcal{F}</math> with  <math>\mathcal{F}=S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})</math> for any <math>1\le i<j\le n</math> '''shifted'''.
 
In order to make the shifting technique work for shadows, we have to prove that shifting does not increase the size of the shadow.
 
{{Theorem|Proposition|
:<math>\Delta S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})\subseteq S_{ij}(\Delta\mathcal{F})</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
We abuse the notation <math>\Delta</math> and let <math>\Delta A=\Delta\{A\}</math> if <math>A</math> is a set instead of a set system.
 
It is sufficient to show that for any <math>A\in\mathcal{F}</math>, <math>\Delta S_{ij}(A)\subseteq S_{ij}(\Delta\mathcal{F})</math>.
 
[[file:Property-shift-shadow.png|600px]]
}}
 
An immediate corollary of the above proposition is that the <math>(i,j)</math>-shifts <math>S_{ij}</math> for any <math>1\le i<j\le n</math> do not increase the size of the shadow.
 
{{Theorem|Corollary|
:<math>|\Delta S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})|\le |\Delta\mathcal{F}|</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
By the above proposition, <math>|\Delta S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})|\le|S_{ij}(\Delta\mathcal{F})|</math>, and we know that <math>S_{ij}</math> does not change the cardinality of a set family, that is, <math>|S_{ij}(\Delta\mathcal{F})|=|\Delta\mathcal{F}|</math>, therefore <math>\Delta S_{ij}(\mathcal{F})|\le|\Delta\mathcal{F}|</math>.
}}
 
;Proof of Kruskal-Katona theorem
We know that shifts never enlarge the shadow, thus it is sufficient to prove the theorem for shifted <math>\mathcal{F}</math>. We then assume <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is shifted.
 
Apply induction on <math>m</math> and for given <math>m</math> on <math>k</math>. The theorem holds trivially for the case that <math>k=1</math> and <math>m</math> is arbitrary.
 
Define
:<math>\mathcal{F}_0=\{A\in\mathcal{F}\mid 1\not\in A\}</math>,
:<math>\mathcal{F}_1=\{A\in\mathcal{F}\mid 1\in A\}</math>.
And let <math>\mathcal{F}_1'=\{A\setminus\{1\}\mid A\in\mathcal{F}_1\}</math>.
 
Clearly <math>\mathcal{F}_0,\mathcal{F}_1\subseteq{X\choose k}</math>, <math>\mathcal{F}_1'\subseteq{X\choose k-1}</math>, and
:<math>|\mathcal{F}|=|\mathcal{F}_0|+|\mathcal{F}_1|=|\mathcal{F}_0|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>.
 
Our induction is based on the following observation regarding the size of the shadow.
{{Theorem|Lemma 1|
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}|\ge|\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
Obviously <math>\mathcal{F}\supseteq\mathcal{F}_1</math> and <math>\Delta\mathcal{F}\supseteq\Delta\mathcal{F}_1</math>.
:<math>\begin{align}
\Delta\mathcal{F}_1
&=\left\{A\in{X\choose k-1}\,\,\bigg|\,\, \exists B\in\mathcal{F}_1, A\subset B\right\}\\
&=\left\{A\in{X\choose k-1}\,\,\bigg|\,\, 1\in A, \exists B\in\mathcal{F}_1, A\subset B\right\}\\
&\quad\, \cup \left\{A\in{X\choose k-1}\,\,\bigg|\,\, 1\not\in A, \exists B\in\mathcal{F}_1, A\subset B\right\}\\
&=\{S\cup\{1\}\mid S\in\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'\}\cup\mathcal{F}_1'.
\end{align}</math>
The union is taken over two disjoint families. Therefore,
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}|\ge|\Delta\mathcal{F}_1|=|\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>.
}}
 
The following property of shifted <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is essential for our proof.
{{Theorem|Lemma 2|
:For shifted <math>\mathcal{F}</math>, it holds that <math>\Delta\mathcal{F}_0\subseteq \mathcal{F}_1'</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
If <math>A\in\Delta\mathcal{F}_0</math> then <math>A\cup\{j\}\in\mathcal{F}_0\subseteq\mathcal{F}</math> for some <math>j>1</math> so that, since <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is shifted, applying the <math>(1,j)</math>-shift <math>S_{1j}</math>, <math>A\cup\{1\}\in\mathcal{F}</math>, thus, <math>A\in\mathcal{F}_1'</math>.
}}
 
We then bound the size of <math>\mathcal{F}_1'</math> as:
 
{{Theorem|Lemma 3|
:If <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is shifted, then
::<math>|\mathcal{F}_1'|\ge{m_k-1\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}-1\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-1}</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
By contradiction, assume that
:<math>|\mathcal{F}_1'|<{m_k-1\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}-1\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-1}</math>.
Then by <math>|\mathcal{F}|=|\mathcal{F}_0|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>, it holds that
:<math>
\begin{align}
|\mathcal{F}_0| &=m-|\mathcal{F}_1'|\\
&>\left\{{m_k\choose k}- {m_k-1\choose k-1}\right\}+\cdots+\left\{{m_t\choose t}- {m_t-1\choose t-1}\right\}\\
&={m_k-1\choose k}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t},
\end{align}</math>
so that, by the induction hypothesis,
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}_0|\ge{m_k-1\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}-1\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-1}>|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>.
On the other hand, by Lemma 2, <math>|\mathcal{F}_1'|\ge|\Delta\mathcal{F}_0|</math>. Thus <math>|\mathcal{F}_1'|\ge|\Delta\mathcal{F}_0|>|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>, a contradiction.
}}
 
Now we officially apply the induction. By Lemma 1,
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}|\ge|\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|</math>.
Note that <math>\mathcal{F}_1'\subseteq{X\choose k-1}</math>, and due to Lemma 3,
:<math>|\mathcal{F}_1'|\ge{m_k-1\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}-1\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-1}</math>,
thus by the induction hypothesis,
:<math>|\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'|\ge{m_k-1\choose k-2}+{m_{k-1}-1\choose k-3}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-2}</math>.
Combining them together, we have
:<math>
\begin{align}
|\Delta\mathcal{F}|
&\ge |\Delta\mathcal{F}_1'|+|\mathcal{F}_1'|\\
&\ge {m_k-1\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-2}+{m_k-1\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t-1\choose t-1}\\
&= {m_k\choose k-1}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-2}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t-1}.
\end{align}</math>
 
:<math>\square</math>
 
=== Shadows of specific sizes ===
The definition of shadow can be generalized to the subsets of any size.
{{Theorem|Definition|
:The '''<math>r</math>-shadow''' of <math>\mathcal{F}</math> is defined as
::<math>\Delta_r\mathcal{F}=\left\{S\mid |S|=r\text{ and }\exists T\in\mathcal{F}, S\subseteq T\right\}</math>.
}}
And the general version of the Kruskal-Katona theorem can be deduced.
{{Theorem|Kruskal-Katona Theorem (general version)|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq {X\choose k}</math> with <math>|\mathcal{F}|=m</math>, and suppose that
::<math>m={m_k\choose k}+{m_{k-1}\choose k-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t}</math>
:where <math>m_k>m_{k-1}>\cdots>m_t\ge t\ge 1</math>. Then for all <math>r</math>, <math>1\le r\le k</math>,
::<math>\left|\Delta_r\mathcal{F}\right|\ge {m_k\choose r}+{m_{k-1}\choose r-1}+\cdots+{m_t\choose t-k+r}</math>.
}}
{{Proof|
Note that for <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq {X\choose k}</math>,
:<math>\Delta_r\mathcal{F}=\underbrace{\Delta\cdots\Delta}_{k-r}\mathcal{F}</math>.
The theorem follows by repeatedly applying the Kruskal-Katona theorem for <math>\Delta\mathcal{F}</math>.
}}
 
=== The Erdős–Ko–Rado theorem, revisited===
To demonstrate the power of the Krulskal-Katona theorem, we show that it actually includes the Erdős–Ko–Rado theorem as a special case. The following elegant proof of the Erdős–Ko–Rado theorem is due to Daykin and Clements independently.
{{Theorem|Erdős–Ko–Rado Theorem|
:Let <math>\mathcal{F}\subseteq {X\choose k}</math> where <math>|X|=n</math> and <math>n\ge 2k</math>. If <math>S\cap T\neq\emptyset</math> for any <math>S,T\in\mathcal{F}</math>, then
::<math>|\mathcal{F}|\le{n-1\choose k-1}</math>.
}}
 
{{Prooftitle|Proof by the Kruskal-Katona theorem|(Daykin 1974, Clements 1976)
By contradiction, suppose that <math>|\mathcal{F}|>{n-1\choose k-1}</math>.
 
We define the dual system
:<math>\mathcal{G}=\{\bar{S}\mid S\in\mathcal{F}\}</math>, where <math>\bar{S}=X\setminus S</math>.
For any <math>S,T\in\mathcal{F}</math>, the condition <math>S\cap T\neq \emptyset</math> is equivalent to <math>S\not\subseteq \bar{T}</math>, so <math>\mathcal{F}</math> and <math>\Delta_k\mathcal{G}</math> are disjoint, thus
:<math>|\mathcal{F}|+|\Delta_k\mathcal{G}|\le{n\choose k}</math>.
Clearly, <math>\mathcal{G}\subseteq {X\choose n-k}</math> and
:<math>|\mathcal{G}|=|\mathcal{F}|>{n-1\choose k-1}={n-1\choose n-k}</math>.
By the Kruskal-Katona theorem, <math>|\Delta_k\mathcal{G}|\ge{n-1\choose k}</math>.
:<math>|\mathcal{F}|+|\Delta_k\mathcal{G}|>{n-1\choose k-1}+{n-1\choose k}={n\choose k}</math>,
a contradiction.
}}

Revision as of 17:50, 26 October 2011

Problem 1

Problem 2

一个图 [math]\displaystyle{ G(V,E) }[/math] 的切 (cut) 是一个边集 [math]\displaystyle{ C\subseteq E }[/math],使得去掉这些边之后 [math]\displaystyle{ G }[/math] 不再连通。

证明:任意一个有 [math]\displaystyle{ m }[/math] 条边的无向图都存在一个大小为 [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{m}{2} }[/math] 的切。

Problem 3

[math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{F}\subseteq{[n]\choose k} }[/math] 为一个 [math]\displaystyle{ k }[/math]-regular family,即 [math]\displaystyle{ \forall i\in[n] }[/math],刚好有 [math]\displaystyle{ k }[/math] 个不同的 [math]\displaystyle{ S\in\mathcal{F} }[/math] 满足 [math]\displaystyle{ i\in S }[/math]

假设 [math]\displaystyle{ k\ge 10 }[/math]。证明:存在一个对 [math]\displaystyle{ [n] }[/math] 的 2着色 [math]\displaystyle{ f:[n]\rightarrow\{0,1\} }[/math] 使得 [math]\displaystyle{ \mathcal{F} }[/math] 中不存在单色的集合 [math]\displaystyle{ S\in\mathcal{F} }[/math]