随机算法 (Spring 2014)/Random Variables and 组合数学 (Spring 2014)/Problem Set 2: Difference between pages

From TCS Wiki
(Difference between pages)
Jump to navigation Jump to search
imported>Etone
 
imported>Etone
 
Line 1: Line 1:
=Random Variable=
== Problem 1==
{{Theorem|Definition (random variable)|
Prove the following identity:
:A random variable <math>X</math> on a sample space <math>\Omega</math> is a real-valued function <math>X:\Omega\rightarrow\mathbb{R}</math>. A random variable X is called a '''discrete''' random variable if its range is finite or countably infinite.
*<math>\sum_{k=1}^n k{n\choose k}= n2^{n-1}</math>.
}}


For a random variable <math>X</math> and a real value <math>x\in\mathbb{R}</math>, we write "<math>X=x</math>" for the event <math>\{a\in\Omega\mid X(a)=x\}</math>, and denote the probability of the event by
(Hint: Use double counting.)
:<math>\Pr[X=x]=\Pr(\{a\in\Omega\mid X(a)=x\})</math>.


The independence can also be defined for variables:
== Problem 2 ==
{{Theorem
(Erdős-Spencer 1974)
|Definition (Independent variables)|
:Two random variables <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> are '''independent''' if and only if
::<math>
\Pr[(X=x)\wedge(Y=y)]=\Pr[X=x]\cdot\Pr[Y=y]
</math>
:for all values <math>x</math> and <math>y</math>. Random variables <math>X_1, X_2, \ldots, X_n</math> are '''mutually independent''' if and only if, for any subset <math>I\subseteq\{1,2,\ldots,n\}</math> and any values <math>x_i</math>, where <math>i\in I</math>,
::<math>\begin{align}
\Pr\left[\bigwedge_{i\in I}(X_i=x_i)\right]
&=
\prod_{i\in I}\Pr[X_i=x_i].
\end{align}</math>
}}


Note that in probability theory, the "mutual independence" is <font color="red">not</font> equivalent with "pair-wise independence", which we will learn in the future.
Let <math>n</math> coins of weights 0 and 1 be given. We are also given a scale with which we may weigh any subset of the coins. Our goal is to determine the weights of coins (that is, to known which coins are 0 and which are 1) with the minimal number of weighings.  


== Expectation ==
This problem can be formalized as follows: A collection <math>S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n]</math> is called '''determining''' if an arbitrary subset <math>T\subseteq[n]</math> can be uniquely determined by the cardinalities <math>|S_i\cap T|, 1\le i\le m</math>.
Let <math>X</math> be a discrete '''random variable'''.  The expectation of <math>X</math> is defined as follows.
{{Theorem
|Definition (Expectation)|
:The '''expectation''' of a discrete random variable <math>X</math>, denoted by <math>\mathbf{E}[X]</math>, is given by
::<math>\begin{align}
\mathbf{E}[X] &= \sum_{x}x\Pr[X=x],
\end{align}</math>
:where the summation is over all values <math>x</math> in the range of <math>X</math>.
}}


== Linearity of Expectation ==
* Prove that if there is a determining collection <math>S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n]</math>, then there is a way to determine the weights of <math>n</math> coins with <math>m</math> weighings.
Perhaps the most useful property of expectation is its '''linearity'''.
* Use pigeonhole principle to show that if a collection <math>S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n]</math> is determining, then it must hold that <math>m\ge \frac{n}{\log_2(n+1)}</math>.


{{Theorem
(This gives a lower bound for the number of weighings required to determine the weights of <math>n</math> coins.)
|Theorem (Linearity of Expectations)|
:For any discrete random variables <math>X_1, X_2, \ldots, X_n</math>, and any real constants <math>a_1, a_2, \ldots, a_n</math>,
::<math>\begin{align}
\mathbf{E}\left[\sum_{i=1}^n a_iX_i\right] &= \sum_{i=1}^n a_i\cdot\mathbf{E}[X_i].
\end{align}</math>
}}
{{Proof| By the definition of the expectations, it is easy to verify that (try to prove by yourself):
for any discrete random variables <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math>, and any real constant <math>c</math>,
* <math>\mathbf{E}[X+Y]=\mathbf{E}[X]+\mathbf{E}[Y]</math>;
* <math>\mathbf{E}[cX]=c\mathbf{E}[X]</math>.
The theorem follows by induction.
}}
The linearity of expectation gives an easy way to compute the expectation of a random variable if the variable can be written as a sum.


;Example
: Supposed that we have a biased coin that the probability of HEADs is <math>p</math>. Flipping the coin for n times, what is the expectation of number of HEADs?
: It looks straightforward that it must be np, but how can we prove it? Surely we can apply the definition of expectation to compute the expectation with brute force. A more convenient way is by the linearity of expectations: Let <math>X_i</math> indicate whether the <math>i</math>-th flip is HEADs. Then <math>\mathbf{E}[X_i]=1\cdot p+0\cdot(1-p)=p</math>, and the total number of HEADs after n flips is <math>X=\sum_{i=1}^{n}X_i</math>. Applying the linearity of expectation, the expected number of HEADs is:
::<math>\mathbf{E}[X]=\mathbf{E}\left[\sum_{i=1}^{n}X_i\right]=\sum_{i=1}^{n}\mathbf{E}[X_i]=np</math>.


The real power of the linearity of expectations is that it does not require the random variables to be independent, thus can be applied to any set of random variables. For example:
== Problem 3 ==
:<math>\mathbf{E}\left[\alpha X+\beta X^2+\gamma X^3\right] = \alpha\cdot\mathbf{E}[X]+\beta\cdot\mathbf{E}\left[X^2\right]+\gamma\cdot\mathbf{E}\left[X^3\right].</math>


However, do not exaggerate this power!
A set of vertices <math>D\subseteq V</math> of graph <math>G(V,E)</math> is a [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Dominating_set ''dominating set''] if for every <math>v\in V</math>, it holds that <math>v\in D</math> or <math>v</math> is adjacent to a vertex in <math>D</math>. The problem of computing minimum dominating set is NP-hard.  
* For an arbitrary function <math>f</math> (not necessarily linear), the equation <math>\mathbf{E}[f(X)]=f(\mathbf{E}[X])</math> does <font color="red">not</font> hold generally.
* For variances, the equation <math>var(X+Y)=var(X)+var(Y)</math> does <font color="red">not</font> hold without further assumption of the independence of <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math>.


==Conditional Expectation ==
* Prove that for every <math>d</math>-regular graph with <math>n</math> vertices, there exists a dominating set with size at most <math>\frac{n(1+\ln(d+1))}{d+1}</math>.


Conditional expectation can be accordingly defined:
* Try to obtain an upper bound for the size of dominating set using Lovász Local Lemma. Is it better or worse than previous one?
{{Theorem
|Definition (conditional expectation)|
:For random variables <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math>,
::<math>
\mathbf{E}[X\mid Y=y]=\sum_{x}x\Pr[X=x\mid Y=y],
</math>
:where the summation is taken over the range of <math>X</math>.
}}


There is also a '''law of total expectation'''.
== Problem 4 ==
{{Theorem
Let <math>H(W,F)</math> be a graph and <math>n>|W|</math> be an integer. It is known that for some graph <math>G(V,E)</math> such that <math>|V|=n</math>, <math>|E|=m</math>, <math>G</math> does not contain <math>H</math> as a subgraph. Prove that for <math>k>\frac{n^2\ln n}{m}</math>, there is an edge <math>k</math>-coloring for <math>K_n</math> that <math>K_n</math> contains no monochromatic <math>H</math>.
|Theorem (law of total expectation)|
:Let <math>X</math> and <math>Y</math> be two random variables. Then
::<math>
\mathbf{E}[X]=\sum_{y}\mathbf{E}[X\mid Y=y]\cdot\Pr[Y=y].
</math>
}}


= Distributions of Coin Flips =
Remark: Let <math>E=\binom{V}{2}</math> be the edge set of <math>K_n</math>. "An edge <math>k</math>-coloring for <math>K_n</math>" is a mapping <math>f:E\to[k]</math>.
We introduce several important probability distributions induced by independent coin flips (independent trials), including: Bernoulli trial, geometric distribution, binomial distribution.


==Bernoulli trial (Bernoulli distribution)==
== Problem 5 ==
Bernoulli trial describes the probability distribution of a single (biased) coin flip. Suppose that we flip a (biased) coin where the probability of HEADS is <math>p</math>. Let <math>X</math> be the 0-1 random variable which indicates whether the result is HEADS. We say that <math>X</math> follows the Bernoulli distribution with parameter <math>p</math>. Formally,
:<math>\begin{align}
X
&=
\begin{cases}
1 & \text{with probability }p\\
0 & \text{with probability }1-p
\end{cases}
\end{align}</math>.


==Geometric distribution==
Let <math>G(V,E)</math> be a cycle of length <math>k\cdot n</math> and let <math>V=V_1\cup V_2\cup\dots V_n</math> be a partition of its <math>k\cdot n</math> vertices into <math>n</math> pairwise disjoint subsets, each of cardinality <math>k</math>.
Suppose we flip the same coin repeatedly until HEADS appears, where each coin flip is independent and follows the Bernoulli distribution with parameter <math>p</math>. Let <math>X</math> be the random variable denoting the total number of coin flips. Then <math>X</math> has the geometric distribution with parameter <math>p</math>. Formally, <math>\Pr[X=k]=(1-p)^{k-1}p</math>.
For <math>k\ge 11</math>, show that there must be an independent set of <math>G</math> containing precisely one vertex from each <math>V_i</math>.


For geometric <math>X</math>, <math>\mathbf{E}[X]=\frac{1}{p}</math>. This can be verified by directly computing <math>\mathbf{E}[X]</math> by the definition of expectations. There is also a smarter way of computing  <math>\mathbf{E}[X]</math>, by using indicators and the linearity of expectations. For <math>k=0, 1, 2, \ldots</math>, let <math>Y_k</math> be the 0-1 random variable such that <math>Y_k=1</math> if and only if none of the first <math>k</math> coin flipings are HEADS, thus <math>\mathbf{E}[Y_k]=\Pr[Y_k=1]=(1-p)^{k}</math>. A key observation is that <math>X=\sum_{k=0}^\infty Y_k</math>. Thus, due to the linearity of expectations,
Hint: you can use Lovász Local Lemma.
:<math>
\begin{align}
\mathbf{E}[X]
=
\mathbf{E}\left[\sum_{k=0}^\infty Y_k\right]
=
\sum_{k=0}^\infty \mathbf{E}[Y_k]
=
\sum_{k=0}^\infty (1-p)^k
=
\frac{1}{1-(1-p)}
=\frac{1}{p}.
\end{align}
</math>
 
==Binomial distribution==
Suppose we flip the same (biased) coin for <math>n</math> times, where each coin flip is independent and follows the Bernoulli distribution with parameter <math>p</math>. Let <math>X</math> be the number of HEADS. Then <math>X</math> has the binomial distribution with parameters <math>n</math> and <math>p</math>. Formally, <math>\Pr[X=k]={n\choose k}p^k(1-p)^{n-k}</math>.
 
A binomial random variable <math>X</math> with parameters <math>n</math> and <math>p</math> is usually denoted by <math>B(n,p)</math>.
 
As we saw above, by applying the linearity of expectations, it is easy to show that <math>\mathbf{E}[X]=np</math> for an <math>X=B(n,p)</math>.
 
=Balls into Bins=
Consider throwing <math>m</math> balls into <math>n</math> bins uniformly and independently at random. This is equivalent to a random mapping <math>f:[m]\to[n]</math>. Needless to say, random mapping is an important random model and may have many applications in Computer Science, e.g. hashing.
 
We are concerned with the following three questions regarding the balls into bins model:
* birthday problem: the probability that every bin contains at most one ball (the mapping is 1-1);
* coupon collector problem: the probability that every bin contains at least one ball (the mapping is on-to);
* occupancy problem: the maximum load of bins.
 
== Birthday Problem==
There are <math>m</math> students in the class. Assume that for each student, his/her birthday is uniformly and independently distributed over the 365 days in a years. We wonder what the probability that no two students share a birthday.
 
Due to the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pigeonhole_principle pigeonhole principle], it is obvious that for <math>m>365</math>, there must be two students with the same birthday. Surprisingly, for any <math>m>57</math> this event occurs with more than 99% probability. This is called the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Birthday_problem '''birthday paradox''']. Despite the name, the birthday paradox is not a real paradox.
 
We can model this problem as a balls-into-bins problem. <math>m</math> different balls (students) are uniformly and independently thrown into 365 bins (days). More generally, let <math>n</math> be the number of bins. We ask for the probability of the following event <math>\mathcal{E}</math>
 
* <math>\mathcal{E}</math>: there is no bin with more than one balls (i.e. no two students share birthday).
 
We first analyze this by counting. There are totally <math>n^m</math> ways of assigning <math>m</math> balls to <math>n</math> bins. The number of assignments that no two balls share a bin is <math>{n\choose m}m!</math>.
 
Thus the probability is given by:
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr[\mathcal{E}]
=
\frac{{n\choose m}m!}{n^m}.
\end{align}
</math>
 
Recall that <math>{n\choose m}=\frac{n!}{(n-m)!m!}</math>. Then
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr[\mathcal{E}]
=
\frac{{n\choose m}m!}{n^m}
=
\frac{n!}{n^m(n-m)!}
=
\frac{n}{n}\cdot\frac{n-1}{n}\cdot\frac{n-2}{n}\cdots\frac{n-(m-1)}{n}
=
\prod_{k=1}^{m-1}\left(1-\frac{k}{n}\right).
\end{align}
</math>
 
There is also a more "probabilistic" argument for the above equation. To be rigorous, we need the following theorem, which holds generally and is very useful for computing the AND of many events.
 
:::{|border="1"
|By the definition of conditional probability, <math>\Pr[A\mid B]=\frac{\Pr[A\wedge B]}{\Pr[B]}</math>. Thus, <math>\Pr[A\wedge B] =\Pr[B]\cdot\Pr[A\mid B]</math>. This hints us that we can compute the probability of the AND of events by conditional probabilities. Formally, we have the following theorem:
'''Theorem:'''
:Let <math>\mathcal{E}_1, \mathcal{E}_2, \ldots, \mathcal{E}_n</math>  be any <math>n</math> events. Then
::<math>\begin{align}
\Pr\left[\bigwedge_{i=1}^n\mathcal{E}_i\right]
&=
\prod_{k=1}^n\Pr\left[\mathcal{E}_k \mid \bigwedge_{i<k}\mathcal{E}_i\right].
\end{align}</math>
'''Proof:'''  It holds that <math>\Pr[A\wedge B] =\Pr[B]\cdot\Pr[A\mid B]</math>. Thus, let <math>A=\mathcal{E}_n</math> and <math>B=\mathcal{E}_1\wedge\mathcal{E}_2\wedge\cdots\wedge\mathcal{E}_{n-1}</math>, then
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr[\mathcal{E}_1\wedge\mathcal{E}_2\wedge\cdots\wedge\mathcal{E}_n]
&=
\Pr[\mathcal{E}_1\wedge\mathcal{E}_2\wedge\cdots\wedge\mathcal{E}_{n-1}]\cdot\Pr\left[\mathcal{E}_n\mid \bigwedge_{i<n}\mathcal{E}_i\right].
\end{align}
</math>
Recursively applying this equation to <math>\Pr[\mathcal{E}_1\wedge\mathcal{E}_2\wedge\cdots\wedge\mathcal{E}_{n-1}]</math> until there is only <math>\mathcal{E}_1</math> left, the theorem is proved. <math>\square</math>
|}
 
Now we are back to the probabilistic analysis of the birthday problem, with a general setting of <math>m</math> students and <math>n</math> possible birthdays (imagine that we live in a planet where a year has <math>n</math> days).
 
The first student has a birthday (of course!). The probability that the second student has a different birthday is <math>\left(1-\frac{1}{n}\right)</math>. Given that the first two students have different birthdays, the probability that the third student has a different birthday from the first two is <math>\left(1-\frac{2}{n}\right)</math>. Continuing this on, assuming that the first <math>k-1</math> students all have different birthdays, the probability that the <math>k</math>th student has a different birthday than the first <math>k-1</math>, is given by <math>\left(1-\frac{k-1}{n}\right)</math>. So the probability that all <math>m</math> students have different birthdays is the product of all these conditional probabilities:
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr[\mathcal{E}]=\left(1-\frac{1}{n}\right)\cdot \left(1-\frac{2}{n}\right)\cdots \left(1-\frac{m-1}{n}\right)
&=
\prod_{k=1}^{m-1}\left(1-\frac{k}{n}\right),
\end{align}
</math>
which is the same as what we got by the counting argument.
 
[[File:Birthday.png|border|450px|right]]
 
There are several ways of analyzing this formular. Here is a convenient one: Due to [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Taylor_series Taylor's expansion], <math>e^{-k/n}\approx 1-k/n</math>. Then
:<math>\begin{align}
\prod_{k=1}^{m-1}\left(1-\frac{k}{n}\right)
&\approx
\prod_{k=1}^{m-1}e^{-\frac{k}{n}}\\
&=
\exp\left(-\sum_{k=1}^{m-1}\frac{k}{n}\right)\\
&=
e^{-m(m-1)/2n}\\
&\approx
e^{-m^2/2n}.
\end{align}</math>
The quality of this approximation is shown in the Figure.
 
Therefore, for <math>m=\sqrt{2n\ln \frac{1}{\epsilon}}</math>, the probability that <math>\Pr[\mathcal{E}]\approx\epsilon</math>.
 
==Coupon Collector ==
Suppose that a chocolate company releases <math>n</math> different types of coupons. Each box of chocolates contains one coupon with a uniformly random type. Once you have collected all <math>n</math> types of coupons, you will get a prize. So how many boxes of chocolates you are expected to buy to win the prize?
 
The coupon collector problem can be described in the balls-into-bins model as follows. We keep throwing balls one-by-one into <math>n</math> bins (coupons), such that each ball is thrown into a bin uniformly and independently at random. Each ball corresponds to a box of chocolate, and each bin corresponds to a type of coupon. Thus, the number of boxes bought to collect <math>n</math> coupons is just the number of balls thrown until none of the <math>n</math> bins is empty.
 
{{Theorem
|Theorem|
:Let <math>X</math> be the number of balls thrown uniformly and independently to <math>n</math> bins until no bin is empty. Then <math>\mathbf{E}[X]=nH(n)</math>, where <math>H(n)</math> is the <math>n</math>th harmonic number.
}}
{{Proof| Let <math>X_i</math> be the number of balls thrown while there are ''exactly'' <math>i-1</math> nonempty bins, then clearly <math>X=\sum_{i=1}^n X_i</math>.
 
When there are exactly <math>i-1</math> nonempty bins, throwing a ball, the probability that the number of nonempty bins increases  (i.e. the ball is thrown to an empty bin) is
:<math>p_i=1-\frac{i-1}{n}.
</math>
<math>X_i</math> is the number of balls thrown to make the number of nonempty bins increases from <math>i-1</math> to <math>i</math>, i.e. the number of balls thrown until a ball is thrown to a current empty bin. Thus, <math>X_i</math> follows the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Geometric_distribution geometric distribution], such that
:<math>\Pr[X_i=k]=(1-p_i)^{k-1}p_i</math>
 
For a geometric random variable, <math>\mathbf{E}[X_i]=\frac{1}{p_i}=\frac{n}{n-i+1}</math>.
 
Applying the linearity of expectations,
:<math>
\begin{align}
\mathbf{E}[X]
&=
\mathbf{E}\left[\sum_{i=1}^nX_i\right]\\
&=
\sum_{i=1}^n\mathbf{E}\left[X_i\right]\\
&=
\sum_{i=1}^n\frac{n}{n-i+1}\\
&=
n\sum_{i=1}^n\frac{1}{i}\\
&=
nH(n),
\end{align}
</math>
where <math>H(n)</math> is the <math>n</math>th Harmonic number, and <math>H(n)=\ln n+O(1)</math>. Thus, for the coupon collectors problem, the expected number of coupons required to obtain all <math>n</math> types of coupons is <math>n\ln n+O(n)</math>.
}}
 
----
 
Only knowing the expectation is not good enough. We would like to know how fast the probability decrease as a random variable deviates from its mean value.
 
{{Theorem
|Theorem|
:Let <math>X</math> be the number of balls thrown uniformly and independently to <math>n</math> bins until no bin is empty. Then <math>\Pr[X\ge n\ln n+cn]<e^{-c}</math> for any <math>c>0</math>.
}}
{{Proof| For any particular bin <math>i</math>, the probability that bin <math>i</math> is empty after throwing <math>n\ln n+cn</math> balls is
:<math>\left(1-\frac{1}{n}\right)^{n\ln n+cn}
< e^{-(\ln n+c)}
=\frac{1}{ne^c}.
</math>
 
By the union bound, the probability that there exists an empty bin after throwing <math>n\ln n+cn</math> balls is
:<math>
\Pr[X\ge n\ln n+cn]
< n\cdot \frac{1}{ne^c}
=e^{-c}.
</math>
}}
 
=== Stable Marriage ===
We now consider the famous [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Stable_marriage_problem '''stable marriage problem'''] or '''stable matching problem''' (SMP). This problem captures two aspects: allocations (matchings) and stability, two central topics in economics.
 
An instance of stable marriage consists of:
* <math>n</math> men and <math>n</math> women;
* each person associated with a strictly ordered ''preference list'' containing all the members of the opposite sex.
Formally, let <math>M</math> be the set of <math>n</math> men and <math>W</math> be the set of <math>n</math> women. Each man <math>m\in M</math> is associated with a permutation <math>p_m</math> of elemets in <math>W</math> and each woman <math>w\in W</math> is associated with a permutation <math>p_w</math> of elements in <math>M</math>.
 
A ''matching'' is a one-one correspondence <math>\phi:M\rightarrow W</math>. We said a man <math>m</math> and a woman <math>w</math> are ''partners'' in <math>\phi</math> if <math>w=\phi(m)</math>.
{{Theorem|Definition (stable matching)|
:A pair <math>(m,w)</math> of a man and woman is a '''blocking pair''' in a matching <math>\phi</math> if <math>m</math> and <math>w</math> are not partners in <math>\phi</math> but
:* <math>m</math> prefers <math>w</math> to <math>\phi(m)</math>, and
:* <math>w</math> prefers <math>m</math> to <math>\phi(w)</math>.
:A matching <math>\phi</math> is '''stable''' if there is no blocking pair in it.
}}
 
It is unclear from the definition itself whether stable matchings always exist, and how to efficiently find a stable matching. Both questions are answered by the following proposal algorithm due to Gale and Shapley.
{{Theorem|The proposal algorithm (Gale-Shapley 1962)|
: Initially, all person are not married;
: in each step (called a '''proposal'''):
:* an arbitrary unmarried man <math>m</math> proposes to the woman <math>w</math> who is ranked highest in his preference list <math>p_m</math> among all the women who has not yet rejected <math>m</math>;
:* if <math>w</math> is still single then <math>w</math> accepts the proposal and is married to <math>m</math>;
:* if <math>w</math> is married to another man <math>m'</math> who is ranked lower than <math>m</math> in her preference list <math>p_w</math> then <math>w</math> divorces <math>m'</math> (thus <math>m'</math> becomes single again and considers himself as rejected by <math>w</math>) and is married to <math>m</math>;
:* if otherwise <math>w</math> rejects <math>m</math>;
}}
 
The algorithm terminates when the last single woman receives a proposal. Since for every pair <math>(m,w)\in M\times W</math> of man and woman, <math>m</math> proposes to <math>w</math> at most once.
The algorithm terminates in at most <math>n^2</math> proposals in the worst case.
 
It is obvious to see that the algorithm retruns a macthing, and this matching must be stable. To see this, by contradiction suppose that the algorithm resturns a macthing <math>\phi</math>, such that two men <math>A, B</math> are macthed to two women <math>a,b</math> in <math>\phi</math> respectively, but <math>A</math> and <math>b</math> prefers each other to their partners <math>a</math> and <math>B</math> respectively. By definition of the algorithm, <math>A</math> would have proposed to <math>b</math> before proposing to <math>a</math>, by which time <math>b</math> must either be single or be matched to a man ranked lower than <math>A</math> in her list (because her final partner <math>B</math> is ranked lower than <math>A</math>), which means <math>b</math> must have accepted <math>A</math>'s proposal, a contradiction.
 
 
We are interested in the average-case performance of this algorithm, that is, the expected number of proposals if everyone's preference list is a uniformly and independently random permutation.
 
The following '''principle of deferred decisions''' is quite useful in analysing performance of algorithm with random input.
{{Theorem|Principle of deferred decisions|
:The decision of random choice in the random input can be deferred to the running time of the algorithm.
}}
 
Apply the principle of deferred decisions, the deterministic proposal algorithm with random permutations as input is equivalent to the following random process:
* At each step, a man <math>m</math> choose a woman <math>w</math> uniformly and independently at random to propose, among all the women who have not rejected him yet. ('''sample without replacement''')
 
We then compare the above process with the following modified process:
* The man <math>m</math> repeatedly samples a uniform and independent woman to propose among all women, until he successfully samples a woman who has not rejected him and propose to her. ('''sample with replacement''')
 
It is easy to see that the modified process (sample with replacement) is no more efficient than the original process (sample without replacement) because it simulates the original process if at each step we only count the last proposal to the woman who has not rejected the man. Such comparison of two random processes by forcing them to be related in some way is called [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Coupling_(probability) coupling].
 
Note that in the modified process (sample with replacement), each proposal, no matter from which man, is going to a uniformly and independently random women. And we know that the algorithm terminated once the last single woman receives a proposal, i.e. once all <math>n</math> women have received at least one proposal. This is the coupon collector problem with proposals as balls (cookie boxes) and women as bins (coupons).
Due to our analysis of the coupon collector problem, the expected number of proposals is bounded by <math>O(n\ln n)</math>.
 
== Occupancy Problem ==
Now we ask about the loads of bins. Assuming that <math>m</math> balls are uniformly and independently assigned to <math>n</math> bins, for <math>1\le i\le n</math>, let <math>X_i</math> be the '''load''' of the <math>i</math>th bin, i.e. the number of balls in the <math>i</math>th bin.
 
An easy analysis shows that for every bin <math>i</math>, the expected load <math>\mathbf{E}[X_i]</math> is equal to the average load <math>m/n</math>.
 
Because there are totally <math>m</math> balls, it is always true that <math>\sum_{i=1}^n X_i=m</math>.
 
Therefore, due to the linearity of expectations,
:<math>\begin{align}
\sum_{i=1}^n\mathbf{E}[X_i]
&=
\mathbf{E}\left[\sum_{i=1}^n X_i\right]
=
\mathbf{E}\left[m\right]
=m.
\end{align}</math>
 
Because for each ball, the bin to which the ball is assigned is uniformly and independently chosen, the distributions of the loads of bins are identical. Thus <math>\mathbf{E}[X_i]</math> is the same for each <math>i</math>. Combining with the above equation, it holds that for every <math>1\le i\le m</math>, <math>\mathbf{E}[X_i]=\frac{m}{n}</math>. So the average is indeed the average!
 
----
 
Next we analyze the distribution of the maximum load. We show that when <math>m=n</math>, i.e. <math>n</math> balls are uniformly and independently thrown into <math>n</math> bins, the maximum load is <math>O\left(\frac{\log n}{\log\log n}\right)</math> with high probability.
 
{{Theorem
|Theorem|
:Suppose that <math>n</math> balls are thrown independently and uniformly at random into <math>n</math> bins. For <math>1\le i\le n</math>, let <math>X_i</math> be the random variable denoting the number of balls in the <math>i</math>th bin. Then
::<math>\Pr\left[\max_{1\le i\le n}X_i \ge\frac{3\ln n}{\ln\ln n}\right] <\frac{1}{n}.</math>
}}
 
{{Proof| Let <math>M</math> be an integer. Take bin 1. For any particular <math>M</math> balls, these <math>M</math> balls are all thrown to bin 1 with probability <math>(1/n)^M</math>, and there are totally <math>{n\choose M}</math> distinct sets of <math>M</math> balls. Therefore, applying the union bound,
:<math>\begin{align}\Pr\left[X_1\ge M\right]
&\le
{n\choose M}\left(\frac{1}{n}\right)^M\\
&=
\frac{n!}{M!(n-M)!n^M}\\
&=
\frac{1}{M!}\cdot\frac{n(n-1)(n-2)\cdots(n-M+1)}{n^M}\\
&=
\frac{1}{M!}\cdot \prod_{i=0}^{M-1}\left(1-\frac{i}{n}\right)\\
&\le \frac{1}{M!}.
\end{align}</math>
 
According to [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Stirling's_approximation Stirling's approximation], <math>M!\approx \sqrt{2\pi M}\left(\frac{M}{e}\right)^M</math>, thus
:<math>\frac{1}{M!}\le\left(\frac{e}{M}\right)^M.</math>
 
[[file:Balls2bins.png|frame|Figure 1]]
 
Due to the symmetry. All <math>X_i</math> have the same distribution.
Apply the union bound again,
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr\left[\max_{1\le i\le n}X_i\ge M\right]
&=
\Pr\left[(X_1\ge M) \vee (X_2\ge M) \vee\cdots\vee (X_n\ge M)\right]\\
&\le
n\Pr[X_1\ge M]\\
&\le n\left(\frac{e}{M}\right)^M.
\end{align}
</math>
 
When <math>M=3\ln n/\ln\ln n</math>,
:<math>\begin{align}
\left(\frac{e}{M}\right)^M
&=
\left(\frac{e\ln\ln n}{3\ln n}\right)^{3\ln n/\ln\ln n}\\
&<
\left(\frac{\ln\ln n}{\ln n}\right)^{3\ln n/\ln\ln n}\\
&=
e^{3(\ln\ln\ln n-\ln\ln n)\ln n/\ln\ln n}\\
&=
e^{-3\ln n+3\ln\ln\ln n\ln n/\ln\ln n}\\
&\le
e^{-2\ln n}\\
&=
\frac{1}{n^2}.
\end{align}
</math>
 
Therefore,
:<math>\begin{align}
\Pr\left[\max_{1\le i\le n}X_i\ge \frac{3\ln n}{\ln\ln n}\right]
&\le n\left(\frac{e}{M}\right)^M
&< \frac{1}{n}.
\end{align}
</math>
}}
 
When <math>m>n</math>, Figure 1 illustrates the results of several random experiments, which show that the distribution of the loads of bins becomes more even as the number of balls grows larger than the number of bins.
 
Formally, it can be proved that for <math>m=\Omega(n\log n)</math>, with high probability, the maximum load is within <math>O\left(\frac{m}{n}\right)</math>, which is asymptotically equal to the average load.

Revision as of 11:26, 9 April 2014

Problem 1

Prove the following identity:

  • [math]\displaystyle{ \sum_{k=1}^n k{n\choose k}= n2^{n-1} }[/math].

(Hint: Use double counting.)

Problem 2

(Erdős-Spencer 1974)

Let [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] coins of weights 0 and 1 be given. We are also given a scale with which we may weigh any subset of the coins. Our goal is to determine the weights of coins (that is, to known which coins are 0 and which are 1) with the minimal number of weighings.

This problem can be formalized as follows: A collection [math]\displaystyle{ S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n] }[/math] is called determining if an arbitrary subset [math]\displaystyle{ T\subseteq[n] }[/math] can be uniquely determined by the cardinalities [math]\displaystyle{ |S_i\cap T|, 1\le i\le m }[/math].

  • Prove that if there is a determining collection [math]\displaystyle{ S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n] }[/math], then there is a way to determine the weights of [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] coins with [math]\displaystyle{ m }[/math] weighings.
  • Use pigeonhole principle to show that if a collection [math]\displaystyle{ S_1,S_1,\ldots,S_m\subseteq [n] }[/math] is determining, then it must hold that [math]\displaystyle{ m\ge \frac{n}{\log_2(n+1)} }[/math].

(This gives a lower bound for the number of weighings required to determine the weights of [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] coins.)


Problem 3

A set of vertices [math]\displaystyle{ D\subseteq V }[/math] of graph [math]\displaystyle{ G(V,E) }[/math] is a dominating set if for every [math]\displaystyle{ v\in V }[/math], it holds that [math]\displaystyle{ v\in D }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ v }[/math] is adjacent to a vertex in [math]\displaystyle{ D }[/math]. The problem of computing minimum dominating set is NP-hard.

  • Prove that for every [math]\displaystyle{ d }[/math]-regular graph with [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] vertices, there exists a dominating set with size at most [math]\displaystyle{ \frac{n(1+\ln(d+1))}{d+1} }[/math].
  • Try to obtain an upper bound for the size of dominating set using Lovász Local Lemma. Is it better or worse than previous one?

Problem 4

Let [math]\displaystyle{ H(W,F) }[/math] be a graph and [math]\displaystyle{ n\gt |W| }[/math] be an integer. It is known that for some graph [math]\displaystyle{ G(V,E) }[/math] such that [math]\displaystyle{ |V|=n }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ |E|=m }[/math], [math]\displaystyle{ G }[/math] does not contain [math]\displaystyle{ H }[/math] as a subgraph. Prove that for [math]\displaystyle{ k\gt \frac{n^2\ln n}{m} }[/math], there is an edge [math]\displaystyle{ k }[/math]-coloring for [math]\displaystyle{ K_n }[/math] that [math]\displaystyle{ K_n }[/math] contains no monochromatic [math]\displaystyle{ H }[/math].

Remark: Let [math]\displaystyle{ E=\binom{V}{2} }[/math] be the edge set of [math]\displaystyle{ K_n }[/math]. "An edge [math]\displaystyle{ k }[/math]-coloring for [math]\displaystyle{ K_n }[/math]" is a mapping [math]\displaystyle{ f:E\to[k] }[/math].

Problem 5

Let [math]\displaystyle{ G(V,E) }[/math] be a cycle of length [math]\displaystyle{ k\cdot n }[/math] and let [math]\displaystyle{ V=V_1\cup V_2\cup\dots V_n }[/math] be a partition of its [math]\displaystyle{ k\cdot n }[/math] vertices into [math]\displaystyle{ n }[/math] pairwise disjoint subsets, each of cardinality [math]\displaystyle{ k }[/math]. For [math]\displaystyle{ k\ge 11 }[/math], show that there must be an independent set of [math]\displaystyle{ G }[/math] containing precisely one vertex from each [math]\displaystyle{ V_i }[/math].

Hint: you can use Lovász Local Lemma.