Limit of a sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an ordered list of events.[1] Each event consists of a mathematical object, which is a number in many cases. In some cases, the sequence tends towards a limit. In this case, the sequence is said to be convergent, otherwise it is divergent.[2]
In a convergent sequence, the absolute difference between the value of the current element and the limit, [math]\displaystyle{ |x_{n} - lim(X)| }[/math] will decrease as the sequence progresses.
Formal Definition
We call [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math] the limit of the sequence [math]\displaystyle{ (x_n) }[/math] if the following condition holds:
- For each real number [math]\displaystyle{ \epsilon \gt 0 }[/math], there exists a natural number [math]\displaystyle{ N }[/math] such that, for every natural number [math]\displaystyle{ n \gt N }[/math], we have [math]\displaystyle{ |x_n - x| \lt \epsilon }[/math].
In other words, for every measure of closeness [math]\displaystyle{ \epsilon }[/math], the sequence's terms are eventually that close to the limit. The sequence [math]\displaystyle{ (x_n) }[/math] is said to converge to or tend to the limit [math]\displaystyle{ x }[/math], written [math]\displaystyle{ x_n \to x }[/math] or [math]\displaystyle{ \lim_{n \to \infty} x_n = x }[/math].
If a sequence converges to some limit, then it is convergent; otherwise it is divergent.
History
The Greek philosopher Zeno of Elea is famous for formulating paradoxes that involve limiting processes.[3]
Leucippus, Democritus, Antiphon, Eudoxus and Archimedes developed the method of exhaustion, which uses an infinite sequence of approximations to determine an area or a volume. Archimedes succeeded in summing what is now called a geometric series.
Newton dealt with series in his works on Analysis with infinite series (written in 1669, circulated in manuscript, published in 1711), Method of fluxions and infinite series (written in 1671, published in English translation in 1736, Latin original published much later) and Tractatus de Quadratura Curvarum (written in 1693, published in 1704 as an Appendix to his Optiks). In the latter work, Newton considers the binomial expansion of (x+o)n which he then linearizes by taking limits (letting o→0).
In the 18th century, mathematicians like Euler succeeded in summing some divergent series by stopping at the right moment; they did not much care whether a limit existed, as long as it could be calculated. At the end of the century, Lagrange in his Théorie des fonctions analytiques (1797) opined that the lack of rigour precluded further development in calculus. Gauss in his etude of hypergeometric series (1813) for the first time rigorously investigated under which conditions a series converged to a limit.
The modern definition of a limit (for any ε there exists an index N so that ...) was given by Bernhard Bolzano (Der binomische Lehrsatz, Prague 1816, little noticed at the time) and by Karl Weierstraß in the 1870s.
References
- ↑ Template:Cite web
- ↑ Courant, Richard (1961). Differential and Integral Calculus Volume I. Glasgow: Blackie & Son, Ltd., p. 29.
- ↑ Craig, Edward (1998) Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Genealogy to Iqbal. London: Routledge, p. 773.